From
a certain perspective, notably that of radical feminism, all gender
socialisation is child abuse.
In
a recent, controversial case brought before the
British courts, a judge took a child out of the care of its mother because it
was deemed that the child was being forced to 'live as a girl' while in fact
identifying as a boy. The mother, the judge claimed, fully believed that she
was supporting the child's right to live as a girl despite having been assigned
the male sex at birth. But, he went on, there was considerable evidence that
the child did not identify as a girl, and that significant emotional harm was
being done by the mother's practices.
This
is one of those cases where we really need chapter and verse, and will
not get it. We have the text of the judgment to go on, and we have
the reactions of trans activists, who have expressed concern about the value
judgments implied in the judgment and the absence of gender specialists
consulted in court. There is a petition seeking to reverse the
decision. Naturally, transphobes of various hues have taken a degree of
satisfaction in the story, as it appears to reinforce their view of the dangers
of currently ascendant ‘trans narratives’.
But
it is a mistake to conduct the argument purely at this level, which necessarily
involves people in smuggling in value judgments as factual claims. What I want
to do is ask: what if everything the judgment says is true? I doubt that it is
that straightforward, but supposing it is: what conclusions should we draw? For
the sake of argument, then, I will assume the factual accuracy of everything
that is claimed by the judge.
In
particular, I will assume that the child identified as a boy, and did not
consent to live as a girl. Or, more precisely, that the child would have
preferred to identify as a boy, and only consented to live as a girl in order
to please his mother. I will assume that the details supplied by the mother
about the trans characteristics of the child are merely a record either of the
mother’s fantasies, or of her own over-interpretation of statements made by her
child, or of her ability to induce certain statements and ways of behaving.
Finally, I will assume that all of the ‘concerns’ expressed by various agencies
are all perfectly well-founded and in no way shaped either by transphobic
valuation or professional ignorance. We can start by acknowledging that this
would indeed be unarguably a case of abuse, regardless of the mother's
sincere intentions.
It
is, of course, not news that the language of liberation can lend itself to
perpetuating abuse. Nor is it at all new for parents to narcissistically use
children as extensions of their own earthly designs, or to expect them to live
in a gender that they do not particularly wish to inhabit. Nor is the specific
phenomenon of mothers preferring their sons to live as girls at all new. What
would have the tincture of novelty is the specific invocation of the language
of trans liberation. And, assuming the judge is correct, this reminds us not to
underestimate the ingenuity of parents in finding ways to fuck up their kids — even
where, as Larkin insists, they may not mean to.
However,
it is also worth being exact about where the abuse would inhere in this case. It
obviously isn't in the “emotional harm” identified by the judge. Emotional harm
is, firstly, a thoroughly nebulous concept and, secondly, a possible product of
abuse rather than identical with the abuse itself. A great deal of abuse of
children by adult carers has no demonstrably harmful result, and lots of
emotional harm results from transactions that we would struggle to qualify as
abusive. If the judgment is correct, for example, then it may be entirely
appropriate that the child was removed from the mother’s care (perhaps the
imperative of keeping families together that guides Social Services practice
prevented appropriate action). And yet this, designed to put an end to abuse,
may turn out to be even more traumatogenic than the abusive treatment itself.
What
would be abusive here would be the extent to which the child became the mother’s
symptom. Every child is, to an extent, its parents’ symptom. Long before it has
been physically conceived, it has been psychically conceived, dreamed up,
wished for, wished on behalf of — always in a gendered way. The child is
written into existence as the subject of its parents’ obscure, complex and to
some extent unconscious desires, long before it can began to articulate any
desire of its own. It becomes a vector for displaced dreams, conflicts and
disappointments between parents, in advance of its own dreams, conflicts and
disappointments. However, in this case, if the judge is correct, then the
mother’s desire for the child to be a girl monopolised any claim to the child’s
identity, leaving him (or her, as the case may be) no space to work it out for
him (or her) self.
And
yet, of course, if we take seriously the benchmark that all gender
socialisation is in some sense abusive, we have no reason to be assured that
the abuse, if that is what was happening, will stop here. After all, the
default assumption that the child is a boy, based on birth-assigned sex, might
also be imposed in just as unilaterally insistent a way, either by the father,
or by the judge, or by Social Services. Perhaps the mother was right to think
that the child wasn’t satisfied with being a boy. Perhaps her mistake was to
rush to the seemingly logical assumption that the child must therefore be a
girl.
Between
parenting, the law, and the pseudo-sympathetic, therapeutic idiom of social
workers, it is not clear that the child’s own questions about gender will be
given space to work themselves out, or will be treated as anything other than a
pathological manifestation of abuse. Of course, we are given to believe that
the judge, the social workers and the father who dispute the claim that the
child is trans, are open-minded about the matter themselves. That, they have
offered the child a choice and observed the choices made in a non-partisan,
open way. This is the sort of thing that adults might believe, but children
never do. That is, adults might be lulled by the soothing neutrality of
legalistic and therapeutic discourses, or the nurturing language of parents,
but children tend to be quite astute and worldly in working out what adults,
cares and authorities desire of them.
Sandor
Ferenczi, writing on the way in which children seek to satisfy their parents’ desires,
referred to an “uncanny clairvoyance”. In a sense, he genuinely seemed to
believe that children could so identify with adults as to completely
internalise their desires without error. This is to lapse into magical
thinking. There is no reason to assume that we are ever more than approximately
right about what others want of us. However, what can be said is that since
their survival depends on understanding what parents want of them, children
become sophisticated interpreters of the words, gestures and silences they are
met with. One by-product of this is that they are so busy preempting,
satisfying or frustrating the desires that others have of them that they never
get to decide what they want for themselves.
The
earliest questions that any child puts to the world are, “where do babies come
from?” and “am I a girl or a boy?” These are existential questions, concerning
sex in both of its main senses. The answers offered by adults are strange, and
would give anyone a complex. Parents are apt to be evasive and anxious in
answering questions about sex, particularly if they are unhappy about their sex
lives. And of course, children are apt to maintain a muted dissent about the
silly fables they are offered, whether it be about storks or mummies and
daddies who love each other very much. So they continue to hunt for the
answers, and construct theories.
Yet
the same parents are usually strangely emphatic, insistent, about who is a boy
and who is a girl, and about the strict relationship between birth-assigned sex
and one’s future gendered life trajectory. They leave no doubt about the
matter, even though many children quietly entertain the gravest doubts. Simply,
where children want knowledge and independence, parents often communicate
ignorance and obedience.
In
this case, according to the court, the mother’s role was not to suppress
the child’s knowledge. Indeed, the judge comments somewhat sniffily on the ‘inappropriate’
extent of the child’s understanding of
sexual anatomy, as conveyed by the father. Instead, the argument is that
the mother coached the child, artificially inducting him into a form of
gendered knowledge that would otherwise only be passed on tacitly,
incrementally, allusively and almost automatically precisely to the extent that
it accorded with ‘normal’ gender socialisation. Yet at the same time, the judge
comments, while the mother was a skilful advocate of trans children in general,
she seemed unable to say much at all about the specific wishes of her own
child. In short, the judgement describes a child discerning and seeking to
fulfil the mother’s desire, rather than the mother defending the child’s
ascertained wish to be trans.
This
suggests that far from breaking with an abusive treatment of the child, the
mother merely inverted it in a way that conformed to her own wishes. We do not,
of course, know what is really true in this case. But we can say that gender
socialisation usually means that someone else has already written your life
story for you: and there is always a sense in which that is unavoidable, and
always a sense in which it is abusive. From the abolitionist perspective, to
imagine a non-abusive form of parenting is to imagine a world without girls and
boys.
The
space between where we are and that horizon is obviously not one that can be
compressed at will. There is still a need to raise children able to survive and
make choices in this world. But one could say as a minimum that to be assigned
the term ‘girl’ or ‘boy’ doesn’t have to be decisive, irreversible, or
exhaustive of all the options. Doctors don’t have to be in such a rush to
assign sex, that — for example — they prematurely force intersex children into
one of the binary classifications. Parents don’t have to be so determined to
produce children adapted to sex assignment that they suppress all doubts or
alternatives. And children can be allowed to suppose that they have a role in
determining whether they are girls, boys or something else, and what that
means.
Even
reaching this comparatively limited goal would require a far-reaching cultural
shift, one that is underway only in certain progressive enclaves. It
necessitates, certainly, further constraints and checks on the automatic
authority of parents over their children. But it also necessitates, as a
minimum, that parents find other ways to desire of and for their children. The
economy of parental desire has to be reconfigured so that they can accommodate
a more capacious and imaginative sense of what it means for a child to thrive
and do well.
Oscar
Wilde spoke of how socialism would relieve us of the sordid necessity of living
for others. Child abuse can be defined as the sordid necessity of living for
one’s parents or caregivers, as if one’s life depended on it. Relieving that
burden, however incrementally, is a start toward a comprehensive liberation for
girls, boys and everyone else.